Customer center

We are a boutique essay service, not a mass production custom writing factory. Let us create a perfect paper for you today!

Example research essay topic: English Language Natural Language - 1,648 words

NOTE: Free essay sample provided on this page should be used for references or sample purposes only. The sample essay is available to anyone, so any direct quoting without mentioning the source will be considered plagiarism by schools, colleges and universities that use plagiarism detection software. To get a completely brand-new, plagiarism-free essay, please use our essay writing service.
One click instant price quote

Is The English Connective or Best Is The English Connective or Best Modelled By Inclusive Or Exclusive Disjunction? We know from our everyday experiences that natural language is plagued by ambiguities and a lack of clarity. Often these can be a source of humour c. f. the age old gag, My dog used to chase an old man on a bicycle.

How did you stop him? I took his bike away. and many would argue that our languages are enriched by the presence of such idiosyncrasies. However, to linguists attempting to implement a model of language and lay down concrete laws, such anomalies present sizeable problems. Consider attempting to model the English language connectives and and or with their logical operator counterparts and we see just such a situation arising. As we shall see in this essay with the examination of one such connective, the English disjunction or, it is perhaps sometimes the case that a rigorous definition in logic is not as simple as might first be thought and that we must look beyond such pragmatic definitions and into the world of semantics, c.

f. Cohens (1971) argument that the English connectives and their logical counterparts are irreconcilably different and a pragmatics approach similar to that of Grice (1967) cannot cope with these differences and thus require some semantic information. A strict interpretation of the word or into its logical operative form would imply that, reminding ourselves that the truth-table for OR is as follows: A B A oor B should be read as meaning that either or both of the clauses being true leads to the disjunction being true. This is known as inclusive disjunction. In natural language we could easily imagine a situation in which this type of disjunction would be the implied meaning for the word or. For example, consider the following sentence: In a course requiring an overall mark of 50 % to pass and consisting of 50 % coursework and 50 % examination, it is possible for a student to pass by gaining 100 % for the coursework or by obtaining 100 % in the exam.

Clearly we do not suppose that a student who scores 100 % in both sections will fail, and therefore the implication here is for inclusive disjunction. However, we could just as easily set up a situation in English in which we use the word or to mean either of the two clauses, but not both. Consider, for example, a traveller coming to a fork in a road. He now has to decide whether he will take the left path or the right path, a situation in which it is quite clearly impossible for him to take both paths simultaneously. Here then, the implication is for exclusive disjunction, in which either of the clauses being true makes the disjunction true, but not both. The truth table for this type of disjunction is as follows: A B A xo It can be seen from the examples given above then, that the word or when used in English can assume various meanings dependent on the context in which it is used.

But is it possible to ascribe one of the above disjunctions to or more than the other, or indeed to rule out one altogether by arguing that the metalinguistic and pragmatic interpretations are not equivalent, i. e. that it is possible to produce an unambiguous linguistic construct for any English sentence using just one of the disjunctions? Gazdar (1977) has claimed that or is unambiguous in English.

He refutes Hurfords (1974) claim that English has two ors (which he argues for on the strength of sentences such as those which were given earlier) by arguing that these apparent different disjunctive's are in fact a result of the logical properties of permission giving sentences, i. e. if it is the case that both clauses together are not allowed, this does not mean that we have an exclusive disjunction. Using the sentence John isnt either patriotic or quixotic, he argues that the ambiguity thesis (the idea that or is both inclusive and exclusive) predicts a reading of the above sentence which he fails to find acceptable, namely that John is both patriotic and quixotic. He forms this from the logical operators thus: ~ (P v Q) = (P. Q) (not exclusive or) = (and) Investigation of the truth tables for these two functions does indeed suggest that one such reading is: John is both patriotic and quixotic, and also the opposite reading John is neither patriotic nor quixotic.

Gazdar says he is unable to find the former interpretation of this sentence and hence or is unambiguously inclusive, apparent instances of exclusive disjunction being incidental of the fact that (P v Q) entails (P v Q). Burton-Roberts (1984) argues against Gazdar in this issue, suggesting that the exclusive reading can be found by interpreting the sentence as John isnt either hes both. This translation suggests that emphasising the negation of either is the key to finding the exclusive interpretation. However, Horn (1985) argues for Gazdar's interpretation of the inclusive nature of or in this sentence. Whilst disagreeing with Gazdar that the exclusive version can be found, he posits that in this case or is inclusive, and that the ambiguity comes not from the or but from the not. He refers to the addition of hes both to the sentence to give the exclusive meaning, by stressing that the not in this case refers to the either, thus arguing that either specifies one or the other, and thus its negation by not in this reading allows the interpretation of not either and hence both that Gazdar rejects.

However, as Browne (1986) points out, Horn provides support for Gazdar in a way in which Gazdar almost certainly would not approve of, since the crux of Horns argument relies upon the ambiguity of the negation operator not, and this is something against which Gazdar has vehemently fought. The argument seen above is not the only case that has been put forward for the un ambiguity of or, and unlike the case above, the next example that we shall examine does not require the ambiguity of the negation operator not. Browne (1986) puts forward the sentence John is either patriotic or quixotic or both and suggests that if or is ambiguous then there are four interpretations of this sentence, since each of the two ors could be thought of as inclusive or exclusive. By investigation of the logical derivations of each interpretation he finds that one interpretation is equivalent to P v Q whilst the other three are equivalent to P v Q.

Browne argues that if the ambiguity thesis is correct then the first derivation, i. e. (P v Q) v (P. Q) must have an interpretation equivalent to P v Q, since they are both derivations of the same ambiguous sentence. However, this first derivation is in fact a very explicit way of expressing inclusive disjunction, thus a contradiction occurs and the ambiguity thesis is proven false, or in this case being univocal. However, having carried out this impressive analysis of the sentence and found this apparent contradiction to the ambiguity of or, Browne concedes that it doesnt actually tell us which reading of or is in fact the correct one, merely that in this instance the two are irreconcilable and ambiguity is not logically possible. To this end he then refers back to the original sentence which we examined here and points to an interpretation of isnt either.

or as inclusive, which is not entailed by the sentence is both... Thus, he argues, it is possible to have a reading of this sentence as inclusive or that does not correspond to exclusive or, and consequently that if either disjunction is a correct model of the English language or it is the inclusive one. Looking at the arguments presented here, it seems that we are still unable to unequivocally ascribe one of the logical connectives to the English language or. The fact that semantically we are able in English to construct sentences which have either meaning precludes such a rigid binding of or to either inclusive or exclusive disjunction, though Gazdar would argue that in such cases it is the logical properties of permission giving sentences such as may which account for the apparent exclusive interpretation.

Gazdar seems to be the strongest opponent of exclusive disjunction in English, indeed he goes further to say; there is no clear evidence that exclusive disjunction has ever been lexical ised in any language. He dismisses as unconvincing Eids claims that Cairene has exclusive disjunction, and citing Karttunens counter-arguments to Collinsons (1948) claim that Finnish has exclusive disjunction concludes by suggesting an important difference between ambiguity and univocal ity plus implicate to explain apparent cases of two ors in natural language. It does seem from the cases put forward by Browne et al that inclusive disjunction is a more accurate model for the metalinguistic or than exclusive disjunction, since we have observed sentences in which the exclusive disjunction cannot be a valid interpretation, whilst no counter-examples of exclusivity without inclusively, except when in connection with permission giving constraints have been produced. Whether such examples exist remains to be seen, though in the meantime the proponents of the inclusive model seem to have the initiative.

However, whilst such arguments may imply that inclusive disjunction is a better model than exclusive disjunction, the fact of the matter is that neither definition can really be considered an accurate definition of the metalinguistic properties of the English word or, and it is thus the opinion of this author that we should not seek to preclude either interpretation in any pragmatic modelling of the English language. approx 1, 500 words Bibliography Browne, A. C. (1986). Univocal OR again Linguistic Inquiry, no. 4. pp 751 - 754 Gazdar, G. (1979). Pragmatics Academic Press


Free research essays on topics related to: c f, english language, put forward, exclusive, natural language

Research essay sample on English Language Natural Language

Writing service prices per page

  • $18.85 - in 14 days
  • $19.95 - in 3 days
  • $23.95 - within 48 hours
  • $26.95 - within 24 hours
  • $29.95 - within 12 hours
  • $34.95 - within 6 hours
  • $39.95 - within 3 hours
  • Calculate total price

Our guarantee

  • 100% money back guarantee
  • plagiarism-free authentic works
  • completely confidential service
  • timely revisions until completely satisfied
  • 24/7 customer support
  • payments protected by PayPal

Secure payment

With EssayChief you get

  • Strict plagiarism detection regulations
  • 300+ words per page
  • Times New Roman font 12 pts, double-spaced
  • FREE abstract, outline, bibliography
  • Money back guarantee for missed deadline
  • Round-the-clock customer support
  • Complete anonymity of all our clients
  • Custom essays
  • Writing service

EssayChief can handle your

  • essays, term papers
  • book and movie reports
  • Power Point presentations
  • annotated bibliographies
  • theses, dissertations
  • exam preparations
  • editing and proofreading of your texts
  • academic ghostwriting of any kind

Free essay samples

Browse essays by topic:

Stay with EssayChief! We offer 10% discount to all our return customers. Once you place your order you will receive an email with the password. You can use this password for unlimited period and you can share it with your friends!

Academic ghostwriting

About us

© 2002-2024 EssayChief.com