Customer center

We are a boutique essay service, not a mass production custom writing factory. Let us create a perfect paper for you today!

Example research essay topic: Lack Of Resources Acute - 2,307 words

NOTE: Free essay sample provided on this page should be used for references or sample purposes only. The sample essay is available to anyone, so any direct quoting without mentioning the source will be considered plagiarism by schools, colleges and universities that use plagiarism detection software. To get a completely brand-new, plagiarism-free essay, please use our essay writing service.
One click instant price quote

INTRODUCTION Is poor citizen´ a contradiction in term? Can we truly speak of a person as complete´ citizen if he strives day and night for his survival in poverty? Can such a person exercise the rights granted to him by the virtue of his membership to the community? Does not the term poverty suggest the failure of social citizenship rights? This concise essay will attempt to briefly answer these questions. In order to be able to sufficiently answer these questions, we need to briefly examine citizenship rights and look at what is that rights give to the person in whom they are vested and determine how poverty effects the citizenship rights of an individual.

Understanding Social Citizenship Rights. To the Greek philosopher Aristotle citizenship was the privileged status for all free men of the city-state. Women and children were not considered citizens and were therefore excluded. Marshall (1950) sees citizenship as a status bestowed upon the full members of a community. Marshall argues that there are no fixed inherent rights in the concept of citizenship, however with historic development rights have come to be associated with citizenship. Marshall identifies three types of rights that he argues to be associated with citizenship in modern democracies.

He calls them civil rights, social rights and political rights. To T. H. Marshall civil rights are rights of citizenship necessary for personal freedom and liberty and include liberty of the person, freedom of speech, thought and faith, the right to own property and to conclude valid contracts, and the right to justice´ (p. 10). In the economic sphere, Marshall considered it a basic civil right to be able to follow the occupation of one´ s choice at the place of one´ s choice, subject only to legitimate restrictions.

Citizenship in the modern democracy is based on universal suffrage and equality before the law (Barbalet 1988). Socio-economic rights have also been reflected in the UN Declaration of Human Rights, as fundamental human rights. These rights are also further elaborated in the UN´ s International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights. These rights include rights to social security in the event of unemployment, sickness, disability or widowhood or old age, rights to food, housing and clothing, rights to medical care and rights to various sorts of education (Jones 1994). These rights also include inter alia the right to work, to just and favourable conditions of employment, to protection against unemployment, to fair remuneration for the work done, and to rest and leisure.

Furthermore, everyone is also said to have the right to freely participate in the cultural life of the community, to enjoy the arts and to share in scientific advancement and its benefits´ . There is a debate in academia as to whether socio-economic rights are fundamental human rights or just citizenship rights granted to the members of a nation-state. Maurice Cranston (1973) argues that for a right to be basic and fundamental human right it must satisfy three conditions of practicality´ , universality´ and paramount importance´ . Cranston argues that socio-economic rights fail the test of practicability´ i.

e. it is not practical for governments of the developing countries to provide all for their inhabitants with goods such as a standard of living adequate for their health and well being´ . Cranston argues that for a right to be fundamental it must be genuinely universal in two ways: it should be a right for all, and right against all. This, Cranston argues, is not true for socio-economic rights as a right to periodic holidays is a rights claimed only by the employees. In the same way socio-economic rights are not against all, as the right to freedom of expression, rather they are rights against a government or an employer. Socio-economic rights pass the test of paramount importance´ , but because of their failure to be practical and universal they are not fundamental human rights, but citizenship rights.

Donnelly (1985) has criticised Cranston with being too simplistic. He argues that to say that right to social security is not universal because not everyone will need to resort to the welfare facility providing social security, is to say that the right to fair trial is not a universal right because not everyone will need it. Welfare goods are considered to be closely associated with social rights as it is through the consumption of welfare goods that a citizen is able to realise the rights granted to him as a citizen and attain well being. There are three reasons for considering welfare goods essential for well being. One, they are regarded necessary for the quality of life people spend. The second reason concerns the obligation of the society to cater to the needs of its members.

Thirdly, considering welfare goods as rights tends to reduce the stigma attached with the benefits given to the people by the government (Jones 1994). UNDERSTANDING THE NATURE OF RIGHTS Needs as Rights It has been argued that people have rights because they have needs. This line of argument is not without problems. First of all what are needs and how can they be defined.

What is the difference between needs and wants? Needs have been argued to have an objective quality that wants do not have. Wants are inherently subjective and various. The needs are said to be limited and identical for all human beings therefore it is practical to take them as rights for all human beings.

Needs are things that are considered crucial to the well-being of the individuals. Can this be argued that people have a right to what they need? This can not be done for the reason that needs in themselves are not complete´ (White 1975, pp. 105 - 7). The argument is that if one says that he has a particular need he can be asked for what. Thus a full statement of needs must have the justification for the need.

Justification aspect of needs is quite important. The essentialness of the need is judged on the basis of justification. Our response to a person´ s claim that he needs a gun will be different if he needs the gun to defend himself against criminals or he needs it to kill someone. Thus, it can be said that the moral claim of the need is entirely dependent on the ends to which they are directed. As already stated, needs can only be treated as human rights if some fundamental, basic needs can be identified that are universally sought by all humans. Real´ s (1971) has identified these basic needs as what he calls the primary goods.

These are the goods that are rational to want for the pursuit of one´ s ends, irrespective of what these ends might be. In this sense basic freedom, and opportunities, income and wealth, can be conceived as providing for fundamental needs´ (Jones 1994, p. 151). Weale (1978) has added specific needs as education and health care to the list of basic human needs. The identification of basic needs has the advantage that these needs are common to all and are required for the pursuits of any purposes. However, if needs are identified as wealth and income than this approach does not help us in establishing needs as rights as it does not assist us in determining who ought to get what. Another way to establish fundamental human needs is to determine them on the basis of what is required by humans to function properly as humans.

We would end up with a list including air, and a certain minimum of food and water. The list may also include a certain degree of autonomy, physical and mental health as the requisite to act as human beings (Deal and Gough 1991). So, it can be said that socio-economic rights are essential for the well being of citizens. The next section examines briefly that what is it that rights offer people and see how poverty effects the ability of individuals to exercise their rights. Rights as Freedoms Rights grant a certain degree of freedom and liberty to the right-holders.

According to the Interest Theory´ of rights to ascribe rights to someone is to say that some aspect of that person´ s well-being is legally or morally shielded against interference and non-assistance´ . The other dominant theory of rights called the Will Theory´ of rights maintains that all rights consist in enjoyment of opportunities for individual or corporate choices each right invests its holder with some degree of control over his or her situation (Kramer et al 1998, p. 2). So it would not be wrong to say that rights are basically about the freedom and choices they offer to the person in whom they vest. Therefore to understand the nature of rights we need to explore the concept of personal liberty and autonomy. Personal liberty has often been defined as freedom or liberty to do or not to do something. This freedom is not unqualified and is restricted in certain cases by the laws of the land and the rights of other individuals.

The rights of individuals to decide and to act as each of them chooses within a circumscribed sphere of life may be described as the right to personal liberty (Jones 1994, p. 122). According to Immanuel Kant human specie is unique in the aspect that it is capable of autonomous conduct. Unlike non-humans who can only act in accordance with their nature, humans can act according to their own conception of what they ought to do i. e. in accordance of their self-imposed rules. So, in Kant´ s view an individual will be deemed to have acted autonomously if he acted in accordance with the rules and principles that he had prescribed for himself, or in other words when he acted rationally.

Kantian concept of autonomy has come to be associated with neutralist´ liberalism i. e. the state should remain unconcerned with the ends to which its citizens may devote their lives (Jones 1989). However the liberals who take that view do not hold that state can and should remain neutral in all matters.

The rules governing the pursuit of these ends may be set by the state, however the citizens should have liberty to pursue their goals in that framework. To neutralist liberals there is a distinction between right´ and good´ . For them right´ provides them the framework within which they are free to pursue their own conceptions of good´ . Berlin (1969) has criticised the Kantian concept of autonomy as too narrow and suited to repressive regimes, which are normally at odds with the basic rights to freedom. Liberal theorists take a more generous view of the concept of autonomy. In their view autonomy is the liberty to make choices, to formulate plans and projects, and to be the architect of one´ s life-goals and ambitions.

J. S. Mill has placed high value on individual liberty´ , the word he has used for autonomy, i. e.

the freedom to individuals to develop their own life in the way they consider proper. Joseph Raz (1986) argues that ideal of personal autonomy is the vision of people controlling, to some degree, their own destiny, fashioning it through successive decisions throughout their lives´ (p. 369). To Raz freedom and autonomy means presence of worthwhile options to the individuals to shape their lives. One finds in the literature that economic limitations have been treated by some authors as constraining the freedom of the poor people, whereas others have regarded them as limits on what people are able´ to do rather than what they are free´ to do. It has also been argued that if lack of material resources amounts to lack of freedom, then the right to do a particular act will mean the right to have the resources to do that act. However, if lack of resources is not lack of freedom than the rights to freedom will be much more modest.

Furthermore, if poverty is not described as un freedom´ , the right to freedom will not include the right to not be impoverished. It has been argued that a way out of this able´ and free´ debate is to argue that poor have a negative freedom to achieve their good´ but they do not have a positive freedom to achieve their well-being. Conclusion From the above discussion it can be said that rights are about liberties that provide the right-holders with the autonomy to make choices. Socio-economic rights should be able to grant citizens with autonomy to shape their socio-economic lives, the way they wish to shape them by selecting the choices available to them.

Do poor citizens have this autonomy? Do they have sufficient socio-economic choices that make them capable to shape their lives as they like? Does lack of resources in any way hampers their pursuit of their own notion of good´ ? Amartya Sen (1992) writes that the resources that a person has represent the extent of freedom he has to consume the various bundles´ of goods available. To use the same argument the lower the level of resources the fewer the choices available for consumption. Fewer the choices available lower the level of freedom granted to the person to act in the way he wishes to act to achieve his own notion of good´ .

Therefore it can be argued that lack of resources decreases the freedom a person has to achieve well being. Freedom is central to the notion of rights; therefore it can be said that with poverty the individual´ s capability to exercise his rights decreases. It can therefore be concluded that poor citizenship is in fact a contradiction. A person can not be poor and a full citizen, exercising the freedoms of action granted to him by virtue of his membership to the state. 31 f


Free research essays on topics related to: choice, acute , lack of resources, fundamental human, socio economic

Research essay sample on Lack Of Resources Acute

Writing service prices per page

  • $18.85 - in 14 days
  • $19.95 - in 3 days
  • $23.95 - within 48 hours
  • $26.95 - within 24 hours
  • $29.95 - within 12 hours
  • $34.95 - within 6 hours
  • $39.95 - within 3 hours
  • Calculate total price

Our guarantee

  • 100% money back guarantee
  • plagiarism-free authentic works
  • completely confidential service
  • timely revisions until completely satisfied
  • 24/7 customer support
  • payments protected by PayPal

Secure payment

With EssayChief you get

  • Strict plagiarism detection regulations
  • 300+ words per page
  • Times New Roman font 12 pts, double-spaced
  • FREE abstract, outline, bibliography
  • Money back guarantee for missed deadline
  • Round-the-clock customer support
  • Complete anonymity of all our clients
  • Custom essays
  • Writing service

EssayChief can handle your

  • essays, term papers
  • book and movie reports
  • Power Point presentations
  • annotated bibliographies
  • theses, dissertations
  • exam preparations
  • editing and proofreading of your texts
  • academic ghostwriting of any kind

Free essay samples

Browse essays by topic:

Stay with EssayChief! We offer 10% discount to all our return customers. Once you place your order you will receive an email with the password. You can use this password for unlimited period and you can share it with your friends!

Academic ghostwriting

About us

© 2002-2024 EssayChief.com